I wanted to understand why picking the most likely is the best you can do (better than choosing randomly from an identical distribution) so I worked it out as follows.
Consider a random experiment with 2 outcomes, 0 and 1.
Let $ \displaystyle E_0 $ be the event that outcome 0 occurs and $ \displaystyle E_1 $ be the event that outcome 1 occurs.
Let $ \displaystyle Pr(E_0) = p $ and $ \displaystyle Pr(E_1) = 1-p $, where $ \displaystyle p $ is some fixed but arbitrary probability.
Assume, without loss of generality, that $ \displaystyle p \ge \frac{1}{2} $ (relabelling the outcomes if necessary).
Consider a joint, independent random experiment intended to predict the outcome of the first.
Let $ \displaystyle F_0 $ be the event that outcome 0 is predicted and $ \displaystyle F_1 $ be the event that outcome 1 is predicted.
Let $ \displaystyle Pr(F_0) = q $ and $ \displaystyle Pr(F_1) = 1-q $
The probability of error is
$ \displaystyle P_{err} = Pr((E_0 \cap F_1) \cup (E_1 \cap F_0)) = Pr(E_0 \cap F_1) + Pr(E_1 \cap F_0) $.
By independence,
$ \displaystyle Pr(E_0 \cap F_1) = Pr(E_0) \cdot Pr(F_1) $
$ \displaystyle Pr(E_1 \cap F_0) = Pr(E_1) \cdot Pr(F_0) $.
So,
$ \displaystyle P_{err} = Pr(E_0) \cdot Pr(F_1) + Pr(E_1) \cdot Pr(F_0) = p(1-q) + (1-p)q $.
We would like to choose $ \displaystyle q\in[0,1] $ to minimize $ \displaystyle P_{err} $. Since $ \displaystyle P_{err} $ is linear in $ \displaystyle q $, the extrema are at the endpoints. Hence, evaluating at $ \displaystyle q=0 $ and $ \displaystyle q=1 $, the minimal $ \displaystyle P_{err} $ is $ \displaystyle 1-p $ at $ \displaystyle q=1 $. Thus the optimal strategy for predicting the outcome of the first experiment is to always (with probability 1) predict the more likely outcome.
Futhermore, on the interval $ \displaystyle p\in[\frac{1}{2}, 1] $, $ \displaystyle P_{err} $ is a strictly decreasing function. That is, the closer $ \displaystyle p $ is to $ \displaystyle \frac{1}{2} $, the worse it can be predicted (the higher $ \displaystyle P_{err} $ is), and the farther $ \displaystyle p $ is from $ \displaystyle \frac{1}{2} $ the better it can be predicted. This is consistent with the information theoretic description of entropy (which has its maximum at $ \displaystyle p=\frac{1}{2} $) as the "average uncertainty in the outcome". Clearly the less uncertain the outcome is, the better we should expect to be able to predict it.
As a concrete example, consider two approaches for predicting an experiment with $ \displaystyle p=.8 $ (i.e. $ \displaystyle E_0 $ occurs with probability .8 and $ \displaystyle E_1 $ occurs with probability .2). In the first approach we always predict $ \displaystyle E_0 $ (hence $ \displaystyle q = Pr(F_0) = 1, Pr(F_1) = 0 $). With this approach we have $ \displaystyle Pr(\{(E_0, F_0)\}) = .8 $, $ \displaystyle Pr(\{(E_0, F_1)\}) = 0 $, $ \displaystyle Pr(\{(E_1, F_0)\}) = .2 $, $ \displaystyle Pr(\{(E_1, F_1)\}) = 0 $. So $ \displaystyle P_{err} = .2 $.
In the second approach we predict randomly according to the distribution of the first experiment (i.e. q = Pr(F_0) = .8, Pr(F_1) = .2). With this approach we have $ \displaystyle Pr(\{(E_0, F_0)\}) = .64 $, $ \displaystyle Pr(\{(E_0, F_1)\}) = .16 $, $ \displaystyle Pr(\{(E_1, F_0)\}) = .16 $, $ \displaystyle Pr(\{(E_1, F_1)\}) = .04 $. So $ \displaystyle P_{err} = .32 $, substantially worse.
--Jvaught 19:59, 26 January 2010 (UTC)